(1)
Welcome – Blackboard Learn. https://www.ole.bris.ac.uk/webapps/portal/execute/tabs/tabAction?tab_tab_group_id=_17_1.
(2)
POLI22202 Unit Summary. https://www.bris.ac.uk/unit-programme-catalogue/UnitDetails.jsa?ayrCode=19%2F20&unitCode=POLI22202.
(3)
Philosophy & Public Affairs.
(4)
Political Theory.
(5)
Ethics.
(6)
Political Studies.
(7)
Politics, Philosophy & Economics.
(8)
Contemporary Political Theory.
(9)
Journal of Political Philosophy.
(10)
Social Philosophy and Policy.
(11)
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/.
(12)
Stilz, A. Why Does the State Matter Morally?’,. In Varieties of Sovereignty and Citizenship; University of Pennsylvania Press, 2012; pp 244–264.
(13)
Simmons, J. The Problem and Its Significance. In Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?; Cambridge University Press, 2005; pp 93–101. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511809286.006.
(14)
Simmons, J. The Theories. In Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?; Cambridge University Press, 2005; pp 102–120. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511809286.007.
(15)
Simmons, A. John. The Principle of Fair Play. Philosophy & Public Affairs 8 (4), 307–337.
(16)
Wolff, R. P. The Conflict between Authority and Autonomy. In In defense of anarchism; Harper Torchbooks: New York, 1976; Vol. Harper essays in philosophy, pp 20–31.
(17)
Hampton, J. Political Philosophy; Westview Press: Boulder, Colo, 1997.
(18)
Raz, J. The Morality of Freedom; Clarendon: Oxford, 1986.
(19)
Raz, J. The Obligation to Obey: Revision and Tradition. In Ethics in the public domain: essays in the morality of law and politics; Clarendon Press: Oxford, 1994.
(20)
Rousseau, J.-J. Book I, Chapters 6-8. In Discours Sur l’Oeconomie Politique; Du Contrat Social: Discourse on Political Economy and the Social Contract; Oxford University Press, 1999.
(21)
Huemer, M. The Problem of Political Authority: An Examination of the Right to Coerce and the Duty to Obey; Palgrave Macmillan: Basingstoke, 2013.
(22)
Morris, C. W. An Essay on the Modern State; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 1998.
(23)
Scott, J. C. Two Cheers for Anarchism: Six Easy Pieces on Autonomy, Dignity, and Meaningful Work and Play; Princeton University Press: Princeton, 2012.
(24)
Simmons, A. J. Moral Principles and Political Obligations; Princeton University Press: Princeton, N.J, 1979.
(25)
Stilz, A. Liberal Loyalty: Freedom, Obligation, and the State; Princeton University Press: Princeton, N.J., 2009.
(26)
Stiltz, A. Robert Paul Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism. In The Oxford Handbook of Classics in Contemporary Political Theory; Levy, J. T., Ed.; 2016.
(27)
Renzo, M. Political Authority and Unjust Wars. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 2019, 99 (2), 336–357. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12487.
(28)
Brennan, J. The Right to a Competent Electorate. The Philosophical Quarterly 2011, 61 (245), 700–724. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9213.2011.699.x.
(29)
Anderson, E. Democracy: Intrinsic vs Instrumental Value. In Contemporary debates in political philosophy; Wiley-Blackwell: Chichester, U.K., 2009; Vol. 11, pp 213–227.
(30)
Christiano, T. The Authority of Democracy*. Journal of Political Philosophy 2004, 12 (3), 266–290. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00200.x.
(31)
Anderson, E. Democracy Intrinsic and Instrumental Value. In Contemporary debates in political philosophy; Wiley-Blackwell: Chichester, U.K., 2009; Vol. 11, pp 213–228.
(32)
Kolodny, N. Rule Over None II: Social Equality and the Justification of Democracy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 2014, 42 (4), 287–336. https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12037.
(33)
Abizadeh, A. On the Demos and Its Kin: Nationalism, Democracy, and the Boundary Problem. American Political Science Review 2012, 106 (04), 867–882. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055412000421.
(34)
Anderson, E. Democracy: Instrumental versus Non-Instrumental Value. In Contemporary debates in political philosophy; Wiley-Blackwell: Chichester, 2009; Vol. 11.
(35)
Anderson, E. The Epistemology of Democracy. Episteme 2006, 3 (1–2), 8–22. https://doi.org/10.3366/epi.2006.3.1-2.8.
(36)
Arneson, R. J. Democracy Is Not Intrinsically Just. In Justice and democracy: essays for Brian Barry; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 2004; pp 40–58.
(37)
Arneson, R. J. Defending the Purely Instrumental Account of Democratic Legitimacy. Journal of Political Philosophy 2003, 11 (1), 122–132. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9760.00170.
(38)
Brennan, J. Polluting The Polls: When Citizens Should Not Vote. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 2009, 87 (4), 535–549. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048400802587309.
(39)
Christiano, T. Democracy as Equality. In Democracy; Blackwell: Malden, Mass, 2002; Vol. Blackwell readings in philosophy, pp 31–50.
(40)
Dworkin, R. Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, Mass, 2000.
(41)
Estlund, D. M. Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework; Princeton University Press: Princeton, 2008.
(42)
Kolodny, N. Rule Over None I: What Justifies Democracy? Philosophy & Public Affairs 2014, 42 (3), 195–229. https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12035.
(43)
Saunders, B. Democracy, Political Equality and Majority Rule. Ethics 2010, 121 (1), 148–177.
(44)
Abizadeh, A. Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders. Political Theory 2008, 36 (1), 37–65.
(45)
Song, S. The Boundary Problem in Democratic Theory: Why the Demos Should Be Bounded by the State. International Theory 2012, 4 (01), 39–68. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1752971911000248.
(46)
Lopez-Guerra, C. Should Expatriates Vote?*. Journal of Political Philosophy 2005, 13 (2), 216–234. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2005.00221.x.
(47)
Goodin, R. E. Enfranchising All Affected Interests, and Its Alternatives. Philosophy & Public Affairs 2007, 35 (1), 40–68. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2007.00098.x.
(48)
Whelan, F. G. Democratic Theory and the Boundary Problem. In Liberal democracy (Nomos XXV); New York University Press: New York, 1983.
(49)
Miller, D. Democracy’s Domain. Philosophy & Public Affairs 2009, 37 (3), 201–228. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2009.01158.x.
(50)
Näsström, S. The Challenge of the All-Affected Principle. Political Studies 2011, 59 (1), 116–134. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2010.00845.x.
(51)
Kolers, A. The Territorial State in Cosmopolitan Justice. Social Theory & Practice 2002, 28 (1), 29–50.
(52)
Buchanan, A. The Morality of Inclusion. Social Philosophy and Policy 1993, 10 (02), 233–257. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0265052500004210.
(53)
Mann, M. The Dark Side of Democracy: The Modern Tradition of Ethnic and Political Cleansing. New Left Review 1999, 235.
(54)
Owen, D. Constituting the Polity, Constituting the Demos: On the Place of the All Affected Interests Principle in Democratic Theory and in Resolving the Democratic Boundary Problem. Ethics & Global Politics 2012, 5 (3), 129–152. https://doi.org/10.3402/egp.v5i3.18617.
(55)
Dahl, R. A. Democracy and Its Critics; Yale University Press: New Haven, 1989.
(56)
Lopez-Guerra, C. Should Expatriates Vote?*. Journal of Political Philosophy 2005, 13 (2), 216–234. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2005.00221.x.
(57)
Owen, D. Resident Aliens, Non-Resident Citizens and Voting Rights. In Citizenship acquisition and national belonging: migration, membership and the liberal democratic state; Palgrave Macmillan: Basingstoke, 2010; pp 52–73.
(58)
Owen, D. Transnational Citizenship and the Democratic State: Modes of Membership and Voting Rights. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 2011, 14 (5), 641–663. https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2011.617123.
(59)
Waldron, J. The Harm in Hate Speech; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, Mass, 2012; Vol. 2009.
(60)
Dworkin, R. Foreword. In Extreme speech and democracy; Oxford University Press: Oxford, 2009.
(61)
Brison, S. J. The Autonomy Defense of Free Speech. Ethics 1998, 108 (2), 312–339. https://doi.org/10.1086/233807.
(62)
Braddon-Mitchell, D.; West, C. What Is Free Speech? Journal of Political Philosophy 2004, 12 (4), 437–460. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00208.x.
(63)
Dworkin, R. Two Concepts of Liberty. In Isaiah Berlin: a celebration; Ullmann-Margalit, E., Margalit, A., Eds.; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, Illinois, 1991.
(64)
Horton, J. The Satanic Verses Controversy: A Brief Introduction. In Liberalism, multiculturalism and toleration; Macmillan: Basingstoke, 1993.
(65)
Jones, P. Respecting Beliefs and Rebuking Rushdie. In Toleration: philosophy and practice; Horton, J., Nicholson, P. P., Eds.; Avebury: Aldershot, 1992.
(66)
Mckinnon, C. Should We Tolerate Holocaust Denial? Res Publica 2007, 13 (1), 9–28. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-006-9013-8.
(67)
MacKinnon, C. A. Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, Mass, 1987.
(68)
Miles, J. K. Social Theory & Practice. 2012, 38 (2), 213–230.
(69)
Mill, J. S.; Little, B. On Liberty; John W. Parker: London, 1859.
(70)
Scanlon, T. M. A Theory of Freedom of Expression. In The difficulty of tolerance: essays in political philosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 2003.
(71)
Waldron, J. Rushdie and Religion. In Liberal rights: collected papers, 1981-1991; Cambridge Universtiy Press: Cambridge, [England], 1993; pp 134–143.
(72)
West, C. The Free Speech Argument against Pornography. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2003, 33 (3), 391–422.
(73)
Smith, W. Democracy, Deliberation and Disobedience. Res Publica 2004, 10 (4), 353–377. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-004-2327-5.
(74)
Delmas, C. Political Resistance: A Matter of Fairness. Law and Philosophy 2014, 33 (4), 465–488. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-013-9189-y.
(75)
Delmas, C. Disobedience, Civil and Otherwise. Criminal Law and Philosophy 2017, 11 (1), 195–211. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9347-9.
(76)
Brownlee, K. Features of a Paradigm Case of Civil Disobedience. Res Publica 2004, 10 (4), 337–351. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-004-2326-6.
(77)
Brownlee, K. Conscience and Conviction: The Case for Civil Disobedience; Oxford University Press: Oxford, 2012.
(78)
Celikates, R. Democratizing Civil Disobedience. Philosophy & Social Criticism 2016, 42 (10), 982–994. https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453716638562.
(79)
Lefkowitz, D. In Defense of Penalizing (but Not Punishing) Civil Disobedience. Res Publica 2017. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-017-9362-5.
(80)
David Lyons. Moral Judgment, Historical Reality, and Civil Disobedience. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1998, 27 (1), 31–49.
(81)
Weinstock, D. How Democratic Is Civil Disobedience? Criminal Law and Philosophy 2016, 10 (4), 707–720. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-015-9367-0.
(82)
Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice; Clarendon Press: Oxford, 1972.
(83)
Rawls, J. Justice as Fairness. In A theory of justice; Belknap Press of Harvard University Press: Cambridge, Mass, 1999; pp 3–46.
(84)
G. A. Cohen. Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1997, 26 (1).
(85)
Parfit, D.; Scanlon, T. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values at UC Berkeley - Lecture Three: Contractualism.
(86)
Freeman, S. R. The Original Position. In Rawls; Routledge: London, 2007; Vol. Routledge philosophers, pp 141–198.
(87)
Arneson, R. J. Against Rawlsian Equality of Opportunity. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 1999, 93 (1), 77–112.
(88)
Freeman, S. Ntroduction. In The Cambridge companion to Rawls; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 2003. https://doi.org/10.1017/CCOL0521651670.001.
(89)
Hampton, J. Contracts and Choices: Does Rawls Have a Social Contract Theory? The Journal of Philosophy 1980, 77 (6). https://doi.org/10.2307/2025640.
(90)
Harsanyi, J. C. The Maximin Principle. In Contemporary political theory: a reader; Farrelly, C. P., Ed.; SAGE: London, 2004; pp 22–31.
(91)
Maffettone, S. Rawls: An Introduction; Polity: Cambridge, 2010.
(92)
Mandle, J. Rawls’s A Theory of Justice: An Introduction; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 2009.
(93)
Mandle, J. What’s Left of Liberalism?: An Interpretation and Defense of Justice as Fairness; Lexington: Lanham, 2000.
(94)
Taylor, R. S. Rawls’s Defense of the Priority of Liberty: A Kantian Reconstruction. Philosophy & Public Affairs 2003, 31 (3), 246–271.
(95)
Anderson, E. S. What Is the Point of Equality? Ethics 1999, 109 (2), 287–337. https://doi.org/10.1086/233897.
(96)
Ronald Dworkin. What Is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1981, 10 (4).
(97)
Cohen, G. A. Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 1995.
(98)
Ryan, C. C. Yours, Mine, and Ours: Property Rights and Individual Liberty. Ethics 1977, 87 (2), 126–141.
(99)
Friedman, M. D. Nozick’s Libertarian Project: An Elaboration and Defense; Bloomsbury Academic: London, 2012.
(100)
Mack, E. Self-Ownership, Marxism, and Egalitarianism. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 2002, 1 (2), 237–276. https://doi.org/10.1177/1470594X02001002004.
(101)
Mack, E. Libertarianism. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Political Philosophy; Klosko, G., Ed.; 2011.
(102)
Mack, E. Self-Ownership, Marxism, and Egalitarianism. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 2002, 1 (1), 75–108. https://doi.org/10.1177/1470594X02001001004.
(103)
Tomasi, J. Free Market Fairness; Princeton University Press: Princeton, 2013.
(104)
Steiner, H. The Natural Right to the Means of Production. The Philosophical Quarterly 1977, 27 (106). https://doi.org/10.2307/2218927.
(105)
Vallentyne, P. Libertarianism and the State. Social Philosophy and Policy 2007, 24 (01). https://doi.org/10.1017/S0265052507070082.
(106)
Stemplowska, Z. Rescuing Luck Egalitarianism. Journal of Social Philosophy 2013, 44 (4), 402–419. https://doi.org/10.1111/josp.12039.
(107)
Lazenby, H. One Kiss Too Many? Giving, Luck Egalitarianism and Other-Affecting Choice*. Journal of Political Philosophy 2009. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2009.00335.x.
(108)
Tan, K.-C. A Defense of Luck Egalitarianism. The Journal of Philosophy 2008, 105 (11), 665–690.
(109)
Otsuka, M. Luck, Insurance, and Equality. Ethics 2002, 113 (1), 40–54. https://doi.org/10.1086/341322.
(110)
Dworkin, R. Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, Mass, 2000.
(111)
Stemplowska, Z. Global Poverty. In Issues in political theory; McKinnon, C., Jubb, R., Tomlin, P., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, United Kingdom, 2019; pp 199–219.
(112)
Zwolinski, M. Sweatshops, Choice, and Exploitation. Business Ethics Quarterly 2007, 17 (4), 689–727. https://doi.org/10.5840/beq20071745.
(113)
Caney, S. Justice beyond Borders: A Global Political Theory; Oxford University Press: Oxford, 2005.
(114)
Gilabert, P. The Duty to Eradicate Global Poverty: Positive or Negative? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2005, 7 (5), 537–550. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-005-6489-9.
(115)
Daskal, S. Confining Pogge’s Analysis of Global Poverty to Genuinely Negative Duties. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2013, 16 (2), 369–391. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-012-9349-4.
(116)
Gauri, V.; Sonderholm, J. Global Poverty: Four Normative Positions. Journal of Global Ethics 2012, 8 (2–3), 193–213. https://doi.org/10.1080/17449626.2012.705787.
(117)
Christiano, T.; Christman, J. P. Distributive Justice at Home and Abroad. In Contemporary debates in political philosophy; Wiley-Blackwell: Chichester, U.K., 2009; Vol. 11.
(118)
Schweiger, G. Recognition Theory and Global Poverty. Journal of Global Ethics 2014, 10 (3), 267–273. https://doi.org/10.1080/17449626.2014.969439.
(119)
Liberto, H. Exploitation and the Vulnerability Clause. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2014, 17 (4), 619–629. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-014-9494-z.
(120)
Wellman, C. H. Immigration and Freedom of Association. Ethics 2008, 119 (1), 109–141. https://doi.org/10.1086/592311.
(121)
Bertram, C. Justifying a Migration Regime from an Impartial Perspective. In Do states have the right to exclude immigrants?; Polity Press, 2018; pp 29–63.
(122)
Abizadeh, A. Democratic Legitimacy and State Coercion: A Reply to David Miller. Political Theory 2010, 38 (1), 121–130.
(123)
Fine, S. The Ethics of Immigration: Self-Determination and the Right to Exclude. Philosophy Compass 2013, 8 (3), 254–268. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12019.
(124)
Wellman, C. H.; Cole, P. Debating the Ethics of Immigration: Is There a Right to Exclude?; Oxford University Press: Oxford, 2011.
(125)
Carens, J. H. The Ethics of Immigration; Oxford University Press: Oxford, 2013.
(126)
Huemer, M. Is There a Right to Immigrate? Social Theory & Practice 2010, 36 (3), 429–461.
(127)
Oberman, K. Immigration as a Human Right. In Migration in political theory: the ethics of movement and membership; Fine, S., Ypi, L., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, 2016. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199676606.003.0003.
(128)
Miller, D. Is There a Human Right to Immigrate? In Migration in political theory: the ethics of movement and membership; Fine, S., Ypi, L., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, 2016. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199676606.001.0001.
(129)
Miller, D. Why Immigration Controls Are Not Coercive: A Reply to Arash Abizadeh. Political Theory 2010, 38 (1), 111–120.
(130)
Okin, S. M. Justice and Gender. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1987, 16 (1), 42–72.
(131)
Brighouse, H.; Olin Wright, E. Strong Gender Egalitarianism. Politics & Society 2008, 36 (3), 360–372. https://doi.org/10.1177/0032329208320566.
(132)
Schouten, G. Restricting Justice: Political Interventions in the Home and in the Market. Philosophy & Public Affairs 2013, 41 (4), 357–388. https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12022.
(133)
Baehr, A. R. Perfectionism, Feminism and Public Reason. Law and Philosophy 2008, 27 (2), 193–222. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-007-9017-3.
(134)
Chambers, C. Sex, Culture, and Justice: The Limits of Choice; Pennsylvania State University Press: University Park, Pennsylvania, 2008.
(135)
Chambers, C. Gender. In Issues in political theory; Oxford University Press: Oxford, 2008; pp 265–288.
(136)
Cohen, G. A. Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice. Philosophy  Public Affairs 1997, 26 (1), 3–30. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.1997.tb00048.x.
(137)
Brake, E. Rawls and Feminism: What Should Feminists Make of Liberal Neutrality? Journal of Moral Philosophy 2004, 1 (3), 293–309. https://doi.org/10.1177/174046810400100305.
(138)
Schouten, G. Citizenship, Reciprocity, and the Gendered Division of Labor. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 2017, 16 (2), 174–209. https://doi.org/10.1177/1470594X15600830.
(139)
Satz, D. Gender. In The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy; Estlund, D., Ed.; 2012.
(140)
Okin, S. M. ‘Forty Acres and a Mule’ for Women: Rawls and Feminism. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 2005, 4 (2), 233–248. https://doi.org/10.1177/1470594X05052540.
(141)
Swift, A. Justice, Luck and the Family. In Unequal chances: family background and economic success; Bowles, S., Gintis, H., Osborne Groves, M., Eds.; Russell Sage Foundation: New York, 2005; pp 256–276.
(142)
Okin, S. M.; Howard, M. Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?; Cohen, J., Nussbaum, M. C., Eds.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, New Jersey, 1999.
(143)
Rawls, J. The Idea of Public Reason Revisited. The University of Chicago Law Review 1997, 64 (3). https://doi.org/10.2307/1600311.
(144)
Simmons, J. The Theories. In Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?; Cambridge University Press, 2005; pp 102–120. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511809286.007.